Friday, February 28, 2014
A Visual Guide to Identifying Genetically Modified Dogs
The above is a takeoff of a Facebook page's "A Visual Guide to Genetically Modified Corn," found here:
IFLS
People are often very misled about what "genetically modified" means. Man has been altering life-forms to suit his needs for thousands and thousands of years through the mechanisms of selective breeding, hybrids, and only lately through direct modification of code.
Corn is a great example of this. It's nature-made predecessor looks nothing like it. The ears are tiny and unusable; the casings of the kernels are thick and chewy. This makes sense for a natural plant, which seeks to spread its seeds, not provide nourishment for man or any other organism directly. The peoples of the Americas, over the course of many generations, turned this wild species into what it is today: a tall plant with ears so heavy they may break the stalks, with easily digestible kernels packed with energy. Modern corn cannot even fertilize any plant besides itself; it is literally impossible for modern corn to grow wild.
What separates this plant from the "GMO" corn of today, created and distributed by Monsanto and other agricultural businesses? The addition of traits is done through direct manipulation of the code, producing specific proteins for specific purposes, rather than through selection of random mutations. Understandably, some people think of this as "unnatural," because it is the result of such direct human intervention, but the host organism itself is unnatural. Actually, direct code manipulation is likely much safer than phenotype selection for traits, as the genes inserted produce known proteins, whereas older methods of genetic modification produced unknown sets of proteins.
How does all this apply to dogs? We have many breeds of dogs, all of them produced by man from a single species: the gray wolf. In fact, technically, wolves are considered the same species as all breeds of dogs because they can mate and produce viable offspring. Dogs are actually a great example of the breakdown of the idea of species as that definition. A chihuaha and a Great Dane are both dogs, but physical mating between the two is nigh impossible. However, it is possible with every breed in between the two, making a range of compatible genetic populations, most of which can also breed with wolves.
If you have a dog (or any domesticated animal, for that matter), you are interacting with a man-made being. You are feeding it man-made food, derived from other organisms created by man out of the building blocks of life - genes - whether the method of design was through careful selection or direct coding.
It not man's nature to adapt to his environment, it is his nature to adapt his environment to himself.
Thursday, February 13, 2014
Deep Time, an Introduction
From Deep Time, created by Matthew J. Wellman and David V. Stewart. Written by David V. Stewart. You can find Matt's blog here: http://thespiritualvoluntaryist.blogspot.com/
Malcom Macbeth stood on the iron walkway extending into what
he called the “nose” of the ship, likening it in his mind to one of the
mechanically propelled airships that humans used before they had made the leap
to space. A glass nose, complete with fire turret, and a glass belly and tail,
used to defend the mighty airship as it delivered it’s precious cargo of living
fire. That time in history seemed so brief to him now, but the flick of a
finger before men abandoned armored flight and mass death for speed and pin-point
accurate murder. The centuries between the rise of agriculture and man’s escape
from his home were a short span of years, yet more intriguing to him than the
entire history of planets conquered since. Part of Malcom yearned to see the
planet of his people’s birth, to see what had become of the ancient ruins- the
castles and cathedrals his ancestors had built- but he knew there was no going
back to the waters of awakening.
He loved more and more to stand in the “nose” these days,
even though his ship was shaped nothing like the old flying fortresses of the
ancients, and this point was just one of many forward-looking positions on the massive
clan ship Icarus. The clear bubble
surrounding the walkway allowed him a greater than one-hundred and eighty
degree view of the cosmos as their vessel pushed its way through deep space. It
was beautiful to him, and he breathed deeply knowing how few men were ever
permitted to grasp the infinite glory and emptiness of space from such a
perspective.
The stars looked strange compared to their dim twinkle on a
planet, when one was not hurtling forward at nearly the speed of light. Here they
blurred like small streaks around him, and yet they also appeared still and
tranquil. They appeared in various shades of blue and indigo, based on how
directly Icarus was travelling toward
a given star, and as Malcom looked off to the left and right he could see the
stars shift to white, and finally red as the ship moved away from them.
The light filled his green eyes, and in the peace he was
able to remember… so much to remember, so many millennia of change on countless
planets to consider and evaluate, and then predict. When he was younger, Malcom
used to retort that the only thing predictable about the human race was its
unpredictability. He’d seen dozens of societies rise, fall, and rise again over
the course of countless generations since he spoke such, and now he had a
different perspective on mankind. One in which, like the weather on a water
planet, everything had its cause and effect and everything occurred in cycles,
if you could only stand far enough back to see it all. And Malcom had stood
back, in a way only the other clan leaders could say they had, and even then,
he wondered if they spent as much time thinking on it as he.
He took everything in the human disposition into account
when he left a world. Plans upon plans. Contingencies upon contingencies. Even
so, like the weather, sometimes there were anomalies, unforeseen events, like a
summer storm upon a desert plain. In the centuries between departure and return,
he knew almost anything could happen, even if the probability was incredibly
low. At the end of every journey, when the quantum gate was completed, and the ship
would jump back instantly to the world they had left just a few months earlier
from their own perspective, Malcom would hold his breath, wondering, and
praying, that he would not pass through to find the old planet had singularized
and become a second Earth; stagnant, inhuman… dead. Returning to find a world
as such once was too much for him. He had paid dearly for his imperfections,
and he still wore the platinum band on his left hand to remind him that he was
not a god, even if the planetside people revered him as such. Eventually, clan
Macbeth would truly be able to account for all the irregularities of humankind.
It was hard to believe that with all the things he had seen,
and all the many years that had passed before his eyes, worlds dying and being
made anew, mankind spreading over the stars, that he had celebrated the his
sixty-fifth ancestral birthday just two months prior. He felt so much older
than that. The life of his race was like a picture gallery, showing slow change
quickly. He ran his hand through his short, grey hair and pondered: I watch the whole of man live and die in
cycles they are nearly oblivious to, and yet I never noticed my hair turning grey
until it was already done doing so.
He fingered the ring on his hand and remembered her. The
smell of her hair as if she was in the nose with him, watching the blue and
indigo stars streak and fill their eyes with wonder. He would never find
another like her again. In all the universe there was only one Deidre, which
made their son all the more precious to him. Even if his heart could allow him
to find love again, it would never happen. The ships were populated by the clan
for a reason. When you spend a hundred years traveling to a new world, you must
leave everyone you love behind… or take them with you. Any woman that would
come aboard Icarus would have to fall
in love with him in the few weeks that he would allow his clan’s vessel to stay
in orbit around a world. He could not leave his ship behind. He had to keep moving.
Keep traveling.
Live forever.
Tuesday, February 4, 2014
Minimum Wage: Moral, Amoral, and Practical Arguments; Ad Hominem Non-Arguments.
The minimum wage as a political
issue has long been a dangerous one to oppose. Recent trends have included
phrases such as “living wage” in addition to a minimum, though the sentiments
are much the same as they were when the minimum wage was first enacted back in
1933 (a law the Supreme Court later found unconstitutional). Proponents of wage
controls generally make moral arguments, primarily that wages should reflect
some correlation to the cost of living at some level of affluence, and that
failing to pay such a wage was an immoral act. Opponents, however, tend to
focus on practical arguments, noting that minimum wage laws create unemployment
among low-skilled and young workers. These arguments do not meet each other
very well, for moral arguments require moral rebuttals, and vice versa.
I. Employer and Employee: An
Amoral Relationship
Let’s break down the moral
arguments for wage controls, whether you choose to define them as “living
wages” or “minimum wages.”
Argument: People require a
certain amount of money or income to live. As such, denying to any person the
level of income necessary to live victimizes them; it is immoral. Therefore,
companies that pay low wages are acting immorally.
Rebuttal: This argument makes
an assumption that individuals and corporations that employ others for
productive purposes have a moral obligation toward some preferable condition. This
is not true, for several reasons. Whenever an employer and employee work
together it is toward some end of production, either a good or a service that
is sold to a third party. Their relationship is voluntary; either party may
exit the relationship when they choose. The worker is not a slave of the
company, so the company has no moral obligation (in a biblical sense) to see to
his end needs.
Businesses pay workers based on
the amount of production they bring to the end goal, not based on the needs of
the worker. Indeed, it would be very difficult to even determine what the end
needs of all the employees are attempt to meet them. The goal is to produce a
product for consumers at a particular price point. This is a thoroughly amoral
condition.
Attempting to prescribe wages
based on the many consequences and costs of life is also a consequentialist
endeavor. The act of paying a worker a low wage is argued as immoral not
because of some universality of preference in wage, but because the consequence
is not a preferable condition. This bad condition is also not universal;
minimum wage may be a boon to one person, who has low living expenses, and be a
very low wage to another who has high living expenses. It’s not quite future
crime, but fairly close to it.
Not addressed in the argument
is the option to not hire somebody at all, which is the result of wage
controls. If a company refuses to hire somebody at all, are they acting
immorally by denying the person a living wage by denying them a job?
Argument: If employers are
unwilling to do what is right, the government must step in and force them to
pay their employees a living wage.
Rebuttal: The most important
moral argument against minimum wage is the means by which it is achieved,
justified in the above argument by the fact that companies do not voluntarily
pay their workers what they are entitled to. Minimum wage laws make the
government a silent third party in any agreement between two individuals, with
the threat of force (death) the consequence for acting outside of the wage
control. If somebody wants to work for less than the minimum wage, they are
legally prohibited from doing so (if you are wondering why anyone would want to work for less than minimum wage,
remember that philosophically wants are always part of a realm of
possibilities, not part of imagination; an individual with no skills might
prefer to work for a low wage rather than be unemployed). In essence, enforcing
minimum wage is an act of violence against the worker and employer.
II. “Right to Life”
Behind both arguments above is
the concept of entitlement, which can be called a “positive right.” As a matter
of philosophy and semantics, I consider all authentic rights to be negative, in
other words, “freedom from” things like theft, murder, or interference in your
personal affairs. Entitlements, which are sometimes called rights by proponents
of such, are usually expressed as a “right to,” such as a right to healthcare,
security, etc. Sometimes, as was the case when Franklin Roosevelt was promoting
the “worker’s bill of rights,” these entitlements are expressed as reflexively
negative, such as the “right to be free from unfair completion,” or the right
to be “free from hunger,” and so on. Of course, freedom from hunger really
means entitlement to food, not freedom to buy food, as freedom requires no
special condition; it is the default.
This concept is important when
understanding the moral claim for a “living wage.” Some argue that it is an
extension of the “right to life,” in so much as you must be able to eat and
find shelter to live. However, an authentic “right to life” really means a
freedom from being murdered by others, and if it is extended beyond such, the
argument becomes self-defeating; you must threaten murder in order to use state
power to tax in order to provide entitlement.
Even ignoring the double-think
involved with such a position, in order for something to be provided, someone
must do the providing. Wage controls place this blame on companies,
organizations whose collective purpose is a good or service, not the welfare of
people everywhere, as stated above. This extension of the right is also
difficult to determine, or make universal (also stated above), because of the
variance of needs across geographic lines and across the myriad of individuals’
choices. Contrast this to a negative right, in which somebody’s right not to be
murdered is very easily determined. You have either been murdered or not; there
is no grey area.
III. Practicality
If the minimum wage were some
cure for poverty, then seventy years’ worth of experimentation in that
department should have yielded some claim to that effect. Instead, poverty
continues as it always has, though the people who are considered poor today are
substantially better off than the middle class when the law was enacted. If it
were really possible to help people out by controlling wages, we could just all
make 100,000 dollars a year and be perfectly happy. Even those who are
proponents of such programs would not go that far, for they know that wage
controls cannot have such an effect. That is why minimum wage rates have
hovered at or slightly below the market equilibrium base rate for unskilled
labor for the past 20 years or so.
The truth is that the minimum
wage does not have a great effect at the moment, positive or negative, because
inflation has made it mostly irrelevant. Even large “evil” companies like
Walmart employ only a small percentage of their workforce at the minimum rate.
If wages were actually raised above the market equilibrium, the effects would
be mostly negative, such as they are. For those near the bottom, some might see
a slight raise. Others, above that wage, would likely see no change whatsoever.
The middle and upper classes would not see their wages go up, for setting a
market minimum for wages does not cause all wages to go up.
The negative is that those who
have low skills, or who are young (these are usually the same group) will find
a tougher job market waiting for them. Employers are less likely to hire an
employee when his or her productive output will not match his wage for some
time while he acquires skills. They may take a chance on an investment of human
capital, but they will need convincing.
IV. You Hate the Poor!
First, I can only feel emotions
toward individuals, not whole classes of people. Second, if I did hate the
poor, I’d be pretty self-hating, as I’ve made far below what the US government
considers the poverty line for the last few years (and I’ve never collected a
dime in entitlements, in case you are wondering, though I would have if it were
possible, given how much I still pay in taxes as a self-employed person). I
don’t hate anyone, which is why I am an advocate for freedom. Yet this is one
of the arguments given against proponents of freedom, the ad-hominem that we “hate
the poor.”
Minimum wage is actually very
bad for the poor and the young, who are usually the same category. It makes
entry into the job market harder, because when you set a minimum wage, you also
set a minimum of production. Workers who do not meet that minimum of
production, usually because they lack skills, have a harder time finding work.
This is the way in which price controls on labor create unemployment.
A worker can gain skills two
ways: through education, or through work experience. The latter must be paid
for in advance, or else financed as debt, making the worker start behind when
he enters the workforce. Of course, if he can gain training and experience
through work itself, he can increase his human capital while making money. Once
he has skills, he can demand higher wages from his employer, of find another
who will pay him according to his value. The minimum wage, therefore, would
only serve him for a limited time while he increases his human capital.
Minimum wage laws are also of
note because, unlike things like direct entitlements, they act violently
against both the poor person and the rich person, buy preventing the poor
person from working for a wage he might find agreeable, at least for a time.
V. Just Like Peter Schiff, You
Think the Intellectually Disabled are Worthless
I’m referencing, of course, a
horribly dishonest Daily Show feature of an interview of Peter Schiff (an
economist and CEO, as well as radio host and advocate for freedom), in which a
four hour interview is reduced to a ninety second heavily edited interchange
that makes Peter sound like he said “mentally retarded” people are worth two
dollars an hour. I could explore the moral problems of the presentation, such
as the fact that before that answer Peter Schiff pondered how anyone could have
such little value, or how the daily show keeps on interns that are unpaid, but
since it is from a comedy show and subject to its own farce I shall make just a
single point.
Of the two people sitting in
that room, only Peter Schiff sees any value with individuals who have intellectual
disabilities. If a company must hire a person with Down syndrome, with its cognitive
impairment component present, at some sort of “living wage,” then that person
will essentially become unemployable, since he or she may not have the
productive capacities to produce that equivalent wage. Schiff, on the other
hand, sees them as valuable to the degree that they can produce, even if it is
limited by their disability. A free market means that every individual, whether
disabled mentally or physically, has the capacity to contribute to society.
With a living wage, many
disabled people may become effectively worthless to society, which they aren’t.
Allowing disabled individuals to work is good for society, even if production
is not great, because it frees up other human capital and also provides a
meaningful service to consumers. It is good for the individuals who are hired,
who may have the opportunity to develop skills, get paid and have financial
goals of their own, and make social connections when they would otherwise be
marginalized in society because of their disability. The disabled don’t have to
be a charity case; they can contribute meaningfully to society, if only they
are permitted.
VI. Walmart as Welfare Queen
I’d like to address another
point that is often thrown around by advocates of things like “living wages,”
and that is the notion that companies who hire unskilled labor for relatively
low wages are somehow gaming the system because their employees consume
entitlements. If you hunt you can probably find the practical data in support
or rejection of the notion, but as a principled argument, you cannot pin upon
McDonalds or Walmart the cost of entitlement spending.
Even if they benefit somehow from
programs such as food stamps, companies that hire low-skill workers did not
create the law, or carry it out using violence. The fact remains that employees
are paid based on their ability to produce; external factors are not relevant.
If there were no entitlements, would workers be able to demand more? The answer
is no, because their pay is determined by how they contribute to earnings.
When making the argument for a
living wage, the question must be also be begged: why should cost of charity
(for that is what paying a worker more than he produces really is) be placed
wholly on those who choose to employ others in productive activities? We as
individuals have the capacity to help the poor directly, no violent state
intervention necessary. If violence is somehow justified (for those of you
willing to sacrifice the means of violence to the end of egalitarianism), why
should it be upon the people who are employers, and not everyone? We could just
as easily (perhaps more so) accomplish the same thing using a negative income
tax, which does not cast into the role of robber-baron those who wish to employ
others.
VII. Conclusion
I hope my points have made you
think, however you may value the minimum wage and its role in society. One
thing to consider when thinking about the raising of the minimum wage is how
much it has been raised in the past, and how much inflation has lowered it over
the years, and how much economic efficiency has in turn prevented the devaluing
of labor. In 1963 the minimum wage was $1.25, but was payable in $25 worth of
today’s dollars in silver (I will provide a useful link to some organized data
on the subject at the bottom). It may seem like we are being quite stingy with
today’s money, but in the past fifty years the economy has become exponentially
more efficient, and that $25 worth of silver will by more goods and services of
a higher quality than existed in the past. The free market, with its ability to
produce more and more for less and less, has been the saving grace of the poor,
not the government regulators, who only have the ability enact violence, even
between two people who have already agreed on a price for labor.
External links:
(I'm not linking to the Daily Show, or the Huffington Post. They don't deserve the traffic.)
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)